
For readers most interested in such details, Francis Wheen’s
biography of Marx, published in 1999, may be a better choice. Mr Stedman
Jones’s book is above all an intellectual biography, which focuses on the
philosophical and political context in which Marx wrote. He completed a
doctorate in philosophy in 1841 and was surrounded by heated discussions about
the consequences of industrialisation and the place of religion in the modern
world. He was an avid reader of The
Economist, while publicly dismissing it as the “European organ of the
aristocracy of finance”.
In contrast to what is often supposed, Marx did not invent
communism. Radicals, including Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (1809-65) and the
Chartist movement in England, had long used language that modern-day readers
would identify as “Marxist”—“to enjoy political equality, abolish property”;
“reserve army of labour” and so forth.
What, then, was his contribution? Much of his time was spent
disagreeing with other radicals, attacking Proudhon in particular, whom he
likened to one of the “bourgeois economists”. Far more significantly, he
attempted to provide an overall theoretical description of how capitalism
worked, especially in “Capital”,
which was published in 1867.
His characterisation of capitalism is elegant in its
simplicity. Each day, he argued, workers produced a greater value of goods than
was necessary to support themselves; capitalists appropriated what was left
over. Workers could not get hold of that surplus because they did not own
capital (machinery, buildings and so on). But as they produced more, they
created more capital, thus reinforcing the domination by the capitalists. A
“system ostensibly resting upon equal and fair exchange could consistently
yield a surplus to one of the parties to the exchange.”
![]() |
Gareth Stedman Jones |
Mr Stedman Jones is an historian with Marxist leanings. As
such the reader might expect a ringing endorsement of the great man’s ideas.
However, in many parts the author is highly critical. For instance, he points
out that Marx displayed “condescension towards developments in political
economy”, a big mistake given how rapidly the field was changing at the time.
More damning, the “Grundrisse”, an
unfinished manuscript which many neo-Marxists see as a treasure trove of
theory, has “defects [in the] core arguments”.
Mr Stedman Jones is even critical of parts of “Capital”. In one passage, Marx set out
to answer a puzzle. Changing levels of supply and demand explain why the price
of a commodity goes up or down, but does not explain why the equilibrium price
of that commodity is what it is. For instance, why are strawberries pricier
than apples?
To solve the puzzle Marx relied on the “labour theory of
value”. He helped prove that the price of a commodity was determined by how
much labour time had gone into it—which showed how workers were exploited.
However, he “arbitrarily ruled out the relative desirability or utility of
commodities,” says Mr Stedman Jones, which would strike most people as the
obvious explanation. The author encapsulates a feeling of many students of
Marx: read the dense, theoretical chapters of “Capital” closely, and no matter how much you try, it is hard to
escape the conclusion that there is plenty of nonsense in there.
The real value of such a work, in Mr Stedman Jones’s eyes,
lies in its documentation of the actual day-to-day life faced by the English
working classes. Marx synthesised an “extraordinary
wealth of statistics, official reports and pieces of press reportage” to
show just how hard life was for many people living in the most industrially
advanced country in the world. Still, even his empirical research had flaws,
something Mr Stedman Jones skirts over. He did not pay enough attention, for
example, to objective measures of living standards (such as real wages), which
by the 1850s were clearly improving.
The overriding impression from this book is that Marx’s
reputation (at least in some quarters) as an unrivalled economist-philosopher
is wide of the mark. Marx had planned to write “Capital” in multiple volumes. He finished the first. But when it
came to writing the second, on realising that he would face insurmountable
intellectual hurdles, he pleaded illness (though seemed quite able to do other
sorts of research). “Karl” was in the thick of the intellectual developments of
the 19th century. But the myth is more impressive than the reality.
![]() |
http://www.economist.com/ |